Few of the assessments of the crisis look at society
and the changes it has undergone in the last two decades. Occasionally mention
is made of growing economic inequality, but what wider impact this might have
is neglected. The proposition, that globalisation and its attendant
developments, above all the post-2008 crisis, have imposed far-reaching changes
on various social strata, often enough without their consent and sometimes even
without the cognitive capacity to identify the nature of the change, tends to
be overlooked. It may sometimes be evoked, but the analysis tends to stop
there. Indeed, there is a kind a tacit assumption that society, especially
society in the democratic state is invariant, is stable and responds to economic,
social, cultural, political processes in much the same way as it did two-three
decades ago.
In this context, both the speed of change and the
multiple areas of life affected are central in their significance. The speed of
change is a vague concept and is notoriously difficult to measure, not least
because it is a subjective experience, nevertheless for older generations it is
a real process. When too many propositions that members of society could take
for granted are likewise affected, then we can identify something of
significance, with consequences for politics and the relationship of society to
power. Crucially, change in one area interacts with change in others,
generating interactions and reciprocal potentiation that are or appear to be
beyond control.
The mechanism identified by complexity theory, that
small causes can have far-reaching outcomes, undermines the linear thinking
that underlies thought-processes and predictability. The great majority of
European societies start from the assumption that processes are linear, that
systems will work as they are supposed to, that cause and effect are broadly in
equilibrium (John Urry is particularly cogent in this area). The reality that linear and non-linear (complex)
processes exist side-by-side and, crucially, that non-linear processes are less
and less subordinated to linearity is very difficult to live with. The further
factor, that thanks to globalisation, events in one part of the world can
radically affect developments in another only exacerbates this.
Most assessments of the crisis recognise that near
complete market freedom has resulted in mounting inequality, but only rarely
have the political implications of this development received their due. Inequality
has several outcomes with the decline of the material well-being that was taken
for granted for decades being the most obvious. But there is another dimension
of inequality that is not regarded by many as central, and this is the growing
sense of injustice and the corresponding resentment at the system – after all,
in a democracy citizenship implies a degree of equality of status, of respect,
of life chances. These are now manifestly absent, albeit the situation is much
more acute in some European states than others.
In this connection, the so-called losers of
globalisation demand particular attention, not least because politically they
have been largely abandoned by their traditional champions, the social
democratic left. The unskilled and semi-skilled manual working class has seen
sizeable losses both in actual jobs and even more galling perhaps, in status.
The emergence of the global labour market has tended to price them out of the
market – labour is much cheaper in China, for example – and they lack the
skills that would allow them to return to active earning, even while global
capitalism has no regard for them as citizens, but sees them as a costly unit
of production.
Their ressentiment,
which may well form part of a hereditary transmission, feeds into the other
sources of perceived injustice analysed here. In effect, they have lost
political representation in the system as it currently operates, so it should
not surprise anyone that they listen to those who do attempt to speak in their
name – the success of Marine Le Pen was certainly based on this at least in
part. Not least, it is interesting to see how the newly elected President and
government of France are using much the same discourses as those pioneered by
the Orbán government in Hungary; something similar can be seen in the President
Obama current campaign on behalf of the “poor” middle classes against the
“rich”.
Those that have adopted the Anglo-Saxon free market
recipe, and this includes much of the former communist world, are probably
worst affected, but the opportunity afforded to some – the few – to pursue
major enrichment is felt throughout Europe. Those at the margin do not like it
and because the dominant ethos is that of liberal consensus, their voices are
ignored.
The flip side of the same process is that the
enrichment of the few has political consequences that likewise call the
effectiveness of democracy into question. When corporate power not only ignores
the bonum publicum, but
simultaneously pressures political actors to take decisions that favour the few
rather than the many, then it can reasonably be argued that an important aspect
of democracy is being flouted. The extensive capture of the political sphere by
partial interests may not be universal, but it is certainly widespread. This is
perfectly understandable in a way. Those with power, economic power in this
case, will do what they can to entrench it and to fight off attempts by
political elites to re-establish control, regardless of what the voters may
actually want. It is in this sense that corporate power is acting against the
interests of democracy.
This illustrates another facet of the crisis. A
generation ago, it was labour that pressurised governments to give it
privileges. Today it is capital. And paradoxically capital is far more
difficult to bring to heel, if indeed it is at all possible, than labour was in
the 1970s. This is overwhelmingly explained by two contingent events. One is
the global mobility of capital, as contrasted with the immobility of labour;
and the other is the end of communism, unreservedly welcome though that was,
which also meant that a counter-discourse to capital and capitalism had
disappeared, thereby making it next to impossible to formulate alternatives to
market fundamentalism before the crisis. The rediscovery of Marx and the
radicalisation of sections of society are belated responses.
Still looking at the unintended consequences of market
fundamentalism, there is the point made by Fukuyama, that the squeeze on the middle classes begins to
threaten democracy, because it is precisely these sections of society that have
the primary interest in the unimpeded functioning of democracy. The argument
regarding the relationship between democracy and the middle classes is an old
one, of course, and there are lessons from the 1930s as to what happens when
the weaker middle strata begin to fear a deterioration – a loss of status, of
power and a decline in incomes. They become vulnerable to radical language,
whether of the left or the right. Generally the right does better because it
claims to address the immediate concerns of those affected and will have
nothing to do with the blandishments of universalism, but that’s another part
of the story.
A second broad area which both affects the crisis and
is exacerbated by it is Europe’s demographic decline (on this and much else see
Krastev). The economically most salient aspect of this has
been frequently highlighted, viz. that a shrinking working population has to
sustain an ever larger post-retirement generation. But that is not where the
story ends. Shrinking societies are generally lacking in self-confidence and
are concerned about their collective futures, their futures as a viable
society, their reproduction as societies. Clearly, the smaller the society, the
more acute this perception will be, meaning that collectivities over a certain
size will be less affected. To this fear can be added the age-old historical
concern shared by all the populations of the smaller states of Europe and most
strongly so in Central Europe that they are fated to die out, unless they make
the greatest effort to avert this.
This fear does not have to have a rational basis for
it to be real, nor does it matter if the fear affects only a portion of the
elite, if that elite is capable of articulating this anxiety and making that
anxiety a part of its plausibility structure. This demographic fear is also a
factor in Europe’s aversion to war and to hard power. Obviously, the
devastations of the 20th century and the way in which this has been
memorialised are central to the aversion to war, but demographic fear adds to
and intensifies it.
The liberal consensus has no remedy to offer, indeed
it may even welcome the disappearance of small groups as obstacles to
universalism, tacitly at any rate.‡ On the other hand, the consensus has
overseen a significant fragmentation, both real and perceived, of society and
in consequence of the polis itself.
The rise of multiple sites of power has been accepted as highly desirable by
the protagonists of the liberal consensus as a welcome development in advancing
democracy. Quite apart from devaluing the role of legislatures (as noted
earlier), the selfsame protagonists ignore the costs. One of these is the
mounting complexity noted in the foregoing – the polis is simply more difficult to understand and, for that matter,
so is good governance, whatever that may be at any one time. This is inevitable
when the number of political actors has increased so greatly. But this
fragmentation has another cost, and this is the weakening of the predictability
and transparency of power, which then adds to the anxiety noted above.
A further facet of the demographic problem is the enormous
expansion of tertiary education. Whereas 30-40 years ago, less then ten percent
of the population received higher education, today it is up to around
two-fifths. But this has produced an unexpected outcome. With the crisis, the
employment prospects of those born after 1985 say have deteriorated radically –
in Spain youth unemployment may be as high as fifty percent. And they are
frequently overqualified for the jobs that they do have. This has resulted in
mounting resentment, understandable in the circumstances, coupled with a
deterioration of the quality of higher education itself – the worst outcome all
round.
It is too early to see all the consequences of this
generational crisis, but inter-generational resentment has already reached the
political agenda; the Occupy movement is a case in point, as were the summer
2011 riots in London. It seems to be highly dangerous for the future that an
entire generation’s entry into adulthood should be the experience of feeling
useless. Some of the victims will necessarily have no faith in citizenship, the
state or democracy, let alone the market. And from this initial experience,
will they actually wish to start a family themselves? Somehow I doubt it.
But this demographic restructuring has had a further
consequence. Even while the economic system as it currently functions is unable
to provide career opportunities and the dignity that goes with it, youth has a
much higher symbolic value than age. This is hardly surprising. The youngest
age cohorts are small and the over 60s are perceived as increasing in size and
living on without a time-limit, at any rate as a generation, not as particular
individuals. This has the paradoxical result that at the very time when an ever
smaller cohort of working age citizens have to provides for a growing old-age
population, the value of the latter is declining. This can hardly add to a
sense of justice on the part of the young.
Immigration and its consequences are a further
exacerbating factor, though one that few would place in this context. In sum,
because multiculturalism has failed (I’ve argued this at considerable length in
my Politics, Illusions, Fallacies),
parallel societies have come into being and these are regarded as highly
disturbing by many in Europe, in as much as unintegrated or semi-integrated
migrants and their descendants challenge local norms and are perceived to be
challenging them. The most visible aspect of this is the growing number of
mosques throughout Europe; what Suleiman the Magnificent failed to achieve by the
sword is seemingly feasible for his latter day successors by peaceful means (of
course).
The further factor that immigrants are perceived to be
the beneficiaries of redistributive justice, which is one of the foundations of
the modern democratic state, and to be doing so disproportionately, only adds
fuel to the flames of resentment. That sections of the elite, the
reality-defining agencies that propagate liberal universalism, insist on
“celebrating” multicultural living creates yet more resentment, because by the
deployment of this discursive instrument, the anxieties of the majority are
dismissed as “racism”. Whereas a century ago, “race” was regarded as natural
phenomenon, with superiority attributed to oneself, this has not only been
turned on its head, but any explanation relying on identity difference counts
as vicious and sinful (the use of religious language here is deliberate).
Besides, somehow it is always minorities that are to
be “celebrated”. Diversity and all the material and symbolic goodies that flow
from it are not really available to majorities or even some minorities (e.g.
historic minorities in Europe). Majorities as citizens pay their taxes, but see
or think they see fewer of the benefits. Redistribution is only legitimate if
it is perceived as fair and if its beneficiaries are accepted as full members
of the community of solidarity. It is precisely this last that the liberal
consensus is determined to eliminate as the most serious obstacle to the single
humanity project.
A further source of anxiety is the loss of freedom
resulting from rapid advances in IT and various forms of surveillance
technology. Much of this is common ground and needs no particular elaboration –
surveillance techniques, face-recognition technology, the merging of
data-bases, the proliferation of registers, pin numbers, credit cards, mobile
phones etc. add up to tools that allow agencies of the state to maintain
control over the citizens in ways that were unthinkable a generation ago. True,
data protection should address this, but the development of technology
constantly outpaces the protection. And even if the level of surveillance is
significantly lower than is thought, the level of fear – a palpable fear of the
unknown – remains high. And fearful sections of society do not make good
democrats, on the contrary.
The relationship between societies as voters and
citizens on the one hand and elites as those exercising power and as
reality-defining agencies on the other has been deteriorating for a while, but
just how far they have deteriorated was only made visible by the crisis. When
seen from below (and here my own experience in Hungary is clearly relevant),
voters feel that elites are remote, not particularly interested in their
concerns, quite prepared to enjoy the material and symbolic benefits of elite
status (like indulging in constant moral legislation), but couldn’t care less
about the fears and anxieties of the citizen in the street. It follows that
these reality-definitions are fraying and not just at the edges, but much more
centrally. It only makes matters worse in the eyes of the citizens that those
who do appear to be addressing their concerns are then reviled as populists,
ethnicists and, maybe, racists.
To this may be added a feeling that existing elites are responsible for the mess – the
sorcerer’s apprentice syndrome – and are quite incapable of finding a solution
to the crisis. In other words, elites are seen by a growing number of citizens
as incompetent. This ties in with a loss of faith in both the state and the
market and that, in turn, has started a process of questioning democracy in its present form itself. The answer
in the eyes of many is a return to the nation-state, to a qualitatively
stronger state structured around a discursively condensed nationhood, with
clear-cut inclusion and exclusion criteria. A survey carried in 2011 in England
was highly revealing in this connection. Nearly half of those polled said that
they would support an English national party as long as it was not associated
with violence.
After
all, if citizenship is to mean anything, it cannot be universal, it cannot
include everyone in the world.
‡ An extreme illustration of this attitude is Kenan
Malik, “Let them die”, in Prospect,
20 November 2000. I quote, “The preservation of dying languages and cultures is
pointless and reactionary. People want to join modernity…” (paywall).
Sch. Gy.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: only a member of this blog may post a comment.